(b. 384 BCE, Stagira, Chalcidice, Greece—d. 322 BCE, Chalcis,
Euboea)
Aristotle (Greek:
Aristoteles) was an ancient Greek philosopher and scientist, and one of the
greatest intellectual figures of Western history. He was the author of a
philosophical and scientific system that became the framework and vehicle for
both Christian Scholasticism and medieval Islamic philosophy. Aristotle’s
intellectual range was vast, covering most of the sciences and many of the
arts, including biology, botany, chemistry, ethics, history, logic,
metaphysics, rhetoric, philosophy of mind, philosophy of science, physics,
poetics, political theory, psychology, and zoology. He was the founder of
formal logic, devising for it a finished system that for centuries was regarded
as the sum of the discipline. Aristotle also pioneered the study of zoology,
both observational and theoretical, in which some of his work remained
unsurpassed until the 19th century. His writings in metaphysics
This statue of Aristotle, the Greek philosopher who
taught Alexander the
Great, stands in the Palazzo Spada in Rome.
Popperfoto/Getty Images
and the philosophy of science continue to be
studied, and his work remains a powerful current in contemporary philosophical debate.
Physics and Metaphysics
Aristotle divided
the theoretical sciences into three groups: physics, mathematics, and theology.
Physics as he understood it was equivalent to what would now be called “natural
philosophy,” or the study of nature; in this sense it encompasses not only the
modern field of physics but also biology, chemistry, geology, psychology, and
even meteorology. Metaphysics, however, is notably absent from Aristotle’s
classification; indeed, he never uses the word, which first appears in the
posthumous catalog of his writings as a name for the works listed after the Physics. He does, however, recognize the
branch of philosophy now called metaphysics. He calls it “first philosophy” and
defines it as the discipline that studies “being as being.”
Aristotle’s contributions to the
physical sciences are less impressive than his researches in the life sciences.
In works such as On Generation and
Corruption and On the Heavens, he
presented a world-picture that included many features inherited from his
pre-Socratic predecessors. From Empedocles (c.
490–430 BCE) he adopted the view that the universe is ultimately composed of
different combinations of the four fundamental elements of earth, water, air,
and fire. Each element is characterized by the possession of a unique pair of
the four elementary qualities of heat, cold, wetness, and dryness: earth is
cold and dry, water is cold and wet, air is hot and wet, and fire is hot and
dry. Each element also has a natural place in an ordered cosmos, and each has
an innate tendency to move toward this natural place. Thus, earthy solids
naturally fall, while
fire, unless prevented, rises ever higher.
Other motions of the elements are possible but are considered “violent.” (A
relic of Aristotle’s distinction is preserved in the modernday contrast between
natural and violent death.)
Aristotle’s vision of the cosmos
also owes much to Plato’s dialogue Timaeus.
As in that work, the Earth is at the centre of the universe, and around it the
Moon, the Sun, and the other planets revolve in a succession of concentric
crystalline spheres. The heavenly bodies are not compounds of the four
terrestrial elements but are made up of a superior fifth element, or
“quintessence.” In addition, the heavenly bodies have souls, or supernatural
intellects, which guide them in their travels through the cosmos.
Even the best of Aristotle’s scientific work has now only a
historical interest. The abiding value of treatises such as the Physics lies not in their particular
scientific assertions but in their philosophical analyses of some of the
concepts that pervade the physics of different eras— concepts such as place,
time, causation, and determinism.
Philosophy of Science
In his Posterior Analytics, Aristotle applies
the theory of the syllogism (a form of deductive reasoning) to scientific and
epistemological ends (epistemology is the philosophy of the nature of
knowledge). Scientific knowledge, he urges, must be built up out of
demonstrations. A demonstration is a particular kind of syllogism, one whose
premises can be traced back to principles that are true, necessary, universal,
and immediately intuited. These first, self-evident principles are related to
the conclusions of science as axioms are related to theorems: the axioms both
necessitate and explain the truths that constitute a science. The most
important axioms, Aristotle thought, would be those that define the proper
subject matter of a science. Thus, among the axioms of geometry would be the
definition of a triangle. For this reason much of the second book of the Posterior Analytics is devoted to
definition.
The account of science in the Posterior Analytics is impressive, but it bears no resemblance to
any of Aristotle’s own scientific works. Generations of scholars have tried in
vain to find in his writings a single instance of a demonstrative syllogism.
Moreover, the whole history of scientific endeavour contains no perfect
instance of a demonstrative science.
Thank you so much.
No comments:
Post a Comment